Some Notes on Section 1.1

Arguments, Premises, and Conclusions

Logic is about ARGUMENTS. People use arguments in reasoning. Informally, arguments can be seen as offering reasons for believing things. Some reasons are good reasons for believing things, and some are not so good.

Sentences and Statements

The things we give reasons for, and the reasons we give for them, can be expressed in SENTENCES. More precisely, they can be expressed in sentences of a certain type: sentences that are either true or false.

Some sentences in English (or any other natural language) have the property that it makes sense to call them true or false. Consider these examples:

  1. Today is Sunday.
  2. There is a cockroach in my raspberry frappé
  3. Two plus two is four.
  4. Two plus two is five.
  5. 2 + 2 = 5.
  6. It will rain tomorrow.
  7. It will rain at 2:00 PM in College Station, Texas, on March 13, 2050.
  8. It rained in College Station, Texas, on March 13, 1950.
  9. The number of people alive at this moment is an even number.
  10. The set of all subsets of an infinite set is of higher cardinality than the set itself.

These are all sentences that it at least makes sense to call true or false in a way that it does not make sense to call any of these sentences true or false:

Try saying "That's true" or "That's not so" about each of these to see the difference.

How do you tell whether a sentence is a statement?

How do you recognize a sentence? That's part of what it is to understand a language. It's very complex, but children can do a pretty good job of this in their native languages by the age of five or so. Here are some sentences:

Even in your own language, it's sometimes not obvious whether something is a sentence. Try these examples.

Or even:

Premises and Conclusions

Here are some arguments:

Each of these arguments consists of sentences, and in fact of sentences of the kind that must be true or false. In addition, one sentence in each of them is distinguished in a certain way. One way to describe the distinction is to say that that sentence is what the argument is trying to prove, or the point of the argument, while all the other sentences are offered as support for that sentence, or reasons for accepting it. We will use the term CONCLUSION for the sentence that's distinguished in this way, and we will call each of the other sentences a PREMISE.

So, how do we tell when an argument is going on, and how do we tell which sentence is the conclusion? Though we'll have a little more to say about that later, we're going to define ARGUMENT in an extremely broad way: an argument is just some sentences (the PREMISES) and another sentence (the CONCLUSION). Formally:

An ARGUMENT is a pair of things:

On this definition, all of the following are arguments:

(You don't have to have more than one premise)

(It doesn't have to be a good argument)

(The premises don't have to have anything to do with the conclusion)

(Strictly speaking, you can have an empty set of premises)

Valid and Invalid Arguments

Here is the single most important definition in this course:

An argument is VALID if and only if it is necessary that if all its premises are true, then its conclusion is true.

A valid argument is an argument in which there is a certain relationship between its premises and its conclusion. That relationship concerns the truth values of the premises and conclusion

"Truth value" is a convenient way of saying "truth or falsehood". Arguments are composed of sentences that are either true or false, so every such sentence has a truth value. Its truth value is "true" if the sentence is true and "false" if the sentence is false (you're not surprised?).

Returning to validity, to say that an argument is valid is to say that the truth values of its premises and its conclusion are related in a certain way: IF the premises are ALL true, THEN the conclusion MUST be true.

Since this is easy to misunderstand, let's spend some time on it. First, it does not say that in an argument, if the premises are true then the conclusion must be true. Instead, it gives the criterion for a valid argument.

How can we tell whether the conclusion must be true if all the premises are true? Well, what's necessary is what can't possibly be otherwise, so if something can possibly be otherwise, then it's not necessary. (That, by the way, was an argument). So, to tell whether an argument is valid, we can:

This sounds like it depends rather a lot on how good we are at thinking up ways that things might be. In fact, we're going to develop some precise ways of doing that for certain arguments as this course proceeds. Let's take a quick look now at how you might proceed, however. Here's an argument:

Sound Arguments

A SOUND argument is just a valid argument with true premises, that is:

An argument is SOUND if and only if it is valid and all its premises are true.

What else can you conclude about an argument on the basis of that definition?

Exercise 1.1

All of these can be answered on the basis of the definitions already given.

i*. Every premise of a valid argument is true
NO: Whether an argument is valid depends on what would happen if the premises WERE all true, non on whether they actually are all true.
ii*. Every invalid argument has a false conclusion
NO: If the premises of a valid argument are not all true, then nothing follows about whether the conclusion is true or not.
iii*. Every valid argument has exactly two premises
NO: An argument (valid or otherwise) may have any number of premises, including only one (or even including zero)
iv*. Some valid arguments have false conclusions
YES: The only thing that can't happen with a valid argument is having the conclusion false when the premises are all true.
v*. Some valid arguments have false conclusions despite having premises that are all true
NO: This almost exactly contradicts the definition of 'valid'.
vi*. A sound argument cannot have a false conclusion
YES: If a valid argument can't have a false conclusion when its premises are all true, and if a sound argument is a valid argument with true premises, then this follows right away.
vii*. Some sound arguments are invalid
NO: Part of the definition of SOUND is VALID ARGUMENT.
viii*. Some unsound arguments have true premises
YES: can you say which ones?
ix*. Premises of sound arguments entail their conclusions
YES: See the definition of ENTAILS.
x*. If an argument has true premises and a true conclusion, then it is sound.
We can talk about this in class

To the Syllabus